They should prune known inferior possibilities like 1 a4
This is an error. You confuse knowing something and believing it because of woefully incomplete and imprecise evidence.
Like a poor chess player making the same error time and time again, you will surely continue to make this error. The above is of course not a chess error: it is an error about reasoning in game theory.
There isn't even a lot of evidence on the move 1. a4. This is itself because of belief, not because of knowledge. People believe it to be pragmatically inferior (quite a different thing to game theoretic inferiority. Most likely, 1. a4 is an optimal move leading to a draw (IMHO)).
Don't get me wrong, it is a good bet that 1. a4 is not better than 1. d4 (say). It would be fair to ascribe a low probability to it being better. But it is no more genuine knowedge than you can have knowledge that a very good horse will win a race.
@MARattigan
Your post #2949 is apparently a response to my post #2945
a few before.
This one: https://www.chess.com/forum/view/general/chess-will-never-be-solved-heres-why?cid=68837185&page=148#comment-68837185
A main point about that post of mine was about the relevance of 'strong' to weak. Strong mathematics. Exact mathematics.
I brought up the relevance of 13 to the 64th power much earlier in the forum.
That and factorials for ways to have 32 squares empty got a good reception.
The relevance of 'strongly solving' is not just as part of the whole process.
Its also relevant for the purpose of contrast.
To understand what is being done with 'weak solving' by comparing with thorough solving. Obvious relevance. 'Meaningfulness'.
Also called 'the big picture'. 'View from the balcony'.